• 제목/요약/키워드: Phrasal verb

검색결과 6건 처리시간 0.014초

구절 동사와 전치사 수반동사의 의미에 따른 음성적 실현 (The Acoustic Realization of Phrasal Verb vs. Verb-preposition)

  • 김희성;송지연;김기호
    • 대한음성학회지:말소리
    • /
    • 제63호
    • /
    • pp.67-84
    • /
    • 2007
  • Verb phrase could have two different meanings according to which is followed after verb; adverb or preposition. The meaning of 'verb+adverb' is deduced from a figurative meaning which is idiomatic expression, and 'verb+preposition' is interpreted as the literal meaning. The purpose of this study is to observe how English native speakers and Korean leaners of English distinguish two sentences of the same word strings with acoustic cues like pause and duration. According to the result, as pause was used for meaning distinction, it was likely that the pause length preceding prepositions was longer than that of following adverbs. To distinguish two sentences of the same word strings, all participants seemed to use pause, verb lengthening and adverb/preposition lengthening. Among them, there is a hierarchical significance; in sequence, pause, verb lengthening, adverb/preposition lengthening.

  • PDF

구절 변환을 위한 한영 동사 사전 구성 (The Construction of Korean-to-English Verb Dictionary for Phrase-to-Phrase Translations)

  • 옥철영;김영택
    • 한국정보과학회 언어공학연구회:학술대회논문집(한글 및 한국어 정보처리)
    • /
    • 한국정보과학회언어공학연구회 1991년도 제3회 한글 및 한국어정보처리 학술대회
    • /
    • pp.44-57
    • /
    • 1991
  • 변환방식의 기계번역은 변환사전에서 제공하는 정보의 종류와 그의 정밀성에 따라서 변환과정의 복잡도와 번역의 질이 결정되어 진다. 사람에 의한 번역은 양국어 사전에서 제공하는 구절 중심의 번역정보를 이용함으로써, 그 번역의 결과는 정확하고 자연스럽다. 본 논문에서는 양국어 사전에서 제공하는 구절 중심의 여러가지 번역정보들을, 한영 기계번역시스템이 이용할 수 있는 형태의 동사 변환사전을 제안하였다. 제안된 변환사전에서는 첫째로, 구절 중심의 번역에서 동사의 역어가 선택되어지는 기준을 제공하여, 변환과정에서 추가적인 의미해석없이도 역어를 효과적으로 선택할 수 있도록 하였다. 둘째로 동사의 역어가 취하는 구체적인 구문구조를 제공하여, 여러 단계의 구조변환의 복잡도를 줄이면서도 두 언어간의 표현방식의 차이점을 해결할 수 있게 하였다.

  • PDF

English Absolutes, Free Adjuncts, and WITH: A Constructional Analysis

  • Yoo, Eun-Jung
    • 한국언어정보학회지:언어와정보
    • /
    • 제12권2호
    • /
    • pp.49-75
    • /
    • 2008
  • English absolutes and free adjuncts, despite their abridged syntactic forms, function as full subordinating adverbial clauses, with their semantic roles varied according to the interpretation of the matrix clauses. This paper investigates how to represent the syntactic structures and semantic variability of absolutes and free adjuncts in a unified way, accounting for overlapping properties among various subtypes of the constructions on the one hand, and differences on the other. In the proposed analysis, the clausal properties of absolutes and free adjuncts are captured by the subject selecting property and the clausal meaning associated with a predicative phrase, thus not calling for a null verb or complementizer. In classifying and defining diverse subtypes of the constructions via type constraints, the present work also provides an account of different uses of with involved in absolutes and free adjuncts.

  • PDF

Distancing the Constraints on Syntactic Variations

  • Choi, Hye-Won
    • 한국언어정보학회지:언어와정보
    • /
    • 제11권1호
    • /
    • pp.77-96
    • /
    • 2007
  • This paper investigates syntactic variations in English such as Dative Alternation, Particle Inversion, and Object Postposition (Heavy NP Shift) within the framework of Optimality Theory, and shows that the same set of morphological, informational, and processing constraints affect all these variations. In particular, it shows that the variants that used to be regarded as ungrammatical are in fact used fairly often in reality, especially when processing or informational conditions are met, and therefore, grammatical judgment may not be always categorical but sometimes gradient. It is argued that the notion of distance in constraint ranking in stochastic OT can effectively explain the gradience and variability of grammaticality in the variation phenomena.

  • PDF

다성적 관점에서 본 프랑스어 속담과 ′의견동사+속담′ 구문의 해독 (A Polyphonic Approach to French Proverbs and the Readings of the Combination ′Opinion Verb + Proverb′)

  • 황경자
    • 인문언어
    • /
    • 제1권1호
    • /
    • pp.275-294
    • /
    • 2001
  • This article aims to define the nature of proverbs from a polyphonic point of view and examine different readings of the complement involved in the combination of a proverb with a verb of personal opinion. An utterer of a proverb is not himself the author of the proverb. He may well be a 'speaker' of a proverb, but from a polyphonic view point he is not an 'enunciator' of the principle that underlies it. When we say that a speaker of a proverb is not its enunciator, we do not simply mean that he is not the author of the 'content' of the proverb he speaks: we mean that he is not the author of its 'form' either. The fact that a proverb loses its proverbial character when one paraphrases it proves that its form is not at the speaker's disposal. But a single factor cannot be held responsible for what a proverb is. As an indicator of the 'wisdom of the nation,' or vox populi, a proverb is the achievement of the 'collective enunciator.' The polyphony inherent in the proverb pits a particular speaker against a collective enunciator. This collective character of the proverb as a vox populi comes from its character as a phrasal denomination. Given that a proverb reflects a collective judgment and not a personal opinion, how do we interpret the combination of a proverb with a verb of personal opinion such as I think that ...\ulcorner Such a combination gives rise to readings at distinct levels: two types of metalinguistic reading and a reading based on the content of the proverb. The first level of reading, being applicative in nature, can be local or general, depending on the speaker's opinion as to the applicability of the proverb to a situation, particular or general. These applicative readings always involve polyphonic dissociation between the speaker and the enunciator. The second level of reading, which depends on the content of the proverb, is the result of the operation of deproverbialization, which makes the proverb lose its denominative status to preserve only its status as a generic phrase. The proverb, thus deproverbialized, looks like the series 'NP + VP.' For this reading, the speaker of the proverb takes into consideration the possibility of attributing a predicate to a nominal syntagm. Here occurs an identity between the speaker and the enunciator. It is not the case, however, that one can deproverbialize just any proverbs. In approaching to a locally typifying generic phrase, a proverb admits of being deproverbialized by an opinion verb only when its form does not render it difficult, either syntactically or metaphorically, to incorporate that proverb into the relevant combination, and when the proverb intrinsically possesses the traits that meet the conditions for the use of the opinion verb at hand. One can also maintain, based on the notion of deproverbialization, that a proverb expresses a collective judgment, a deproverbialized individual judgment.

  • PDF

A Bi-clausal Account of English 'to'-Modal Auxiliary Verbs

  • Hong, Sungshim
    • 한국언어정보학회지:언어와정보
    • /
    • 제18권1호
    • /
    • pp.33-52
    • /
    • 2014
  • This paper proposes a unified structural account of some instances of the English Modals and Semi-auxiliaries. The classification and the syntactic/structural description of the English Modal auxiliary verbs and verb-related elements have long been the center for many proposals in the history of generative syntax. According to van Gelderen (1993) and Lightfoot (2002), it was sometime around 1380 that the Tense-node (T) appeared in the phrasal structures of the English language, and the T-node is under which the English Modal auxiliaries occupy. Closely related is the existing evidence that English Modals were used as main verbs up to the early sixteenth century (Lightfoot 1991, Han 2000). This paper argues for a bi-clausal approach to English Modal auxiliaries with the infinitival particle 'to' such as 'ought to' 'used to' and 'dare (to)' 'need (to)', etc. and Semi-auxiliaries including 'be to' and 'have to'. More specifically, 'ought' in 'ought to' constructions, for instance, undergoes V-to-T movement within the matrix clause, just like 'HAVEAux' and all instances of 'BE', whereas 'to' occupies the T position of the embedded complement clause. By proposing the bi-clausal account, Radford's (2004, 2009) problems can be solved. Further, the historical motivation for the account takes a stance along with Norde (2009) and Brinton & Traugott (2005) in that Radford's (2004, 2009) syncretization of the two positions of the infinitival particle 'to' is no different from the 'boundary loss' in the process of Grammariticalization. This line of argument supports Krug's (2011), and in turn Bolinger's(1980) generalization on Auxiliaryhood, while providing a novel insight into Head movement of V-to-T in Present Day English.

  • PDF